Skip to main content.
Bard HAC
Bard HAC
  • About sub-menuAbout
    Hannah Arendt

    “There are no dangerous thoughts; thinking itself is dangerous.”

    Join HAC
    • About the HAC
      • About Hannah Arendt
      • Book Roger
      • Our Team
      • Our Location
  • Programs sub-menuPrograms
    Hannah Arendt
    • Our Programs
    • Courage to Be
    • Democracy Innovation Hub
    • Virtual Reading Group
    • Dialogue Groups
    • HA Personal Library
    • Affiliated Programs
    • Hannah Arendt Humanities Network
    • Meanings of October 27th
    • Lapham's Quarterly
  • Academics sub-menuAcademics
    Hannah Arendt

    “Storytelling reveals meaning without committing the error of defining it.”

    • Academics at HAC
    • Undergraduate Courses
  • Fellowships sub-menuFellowships
    HAC Fellows

    “Action without a name, a 'who' attached to it, is meaningless.”

    • Fellowships
    • Senior Fellows
    • Associate Fellows
    • Student Fellowships
  • Conferences sub-menuConferences
    JOY: Loving the World in Dark Times Conference poster

    Fall Conference 2025
    “JOY: Loving the World in Dark Times”

    October 16 – 17

    Read More Here
    • Conferences
    • Past Conferences
    • Registration
    • Our Location
    • De Gruyter-Arendt Center Lecture in Political Thinking
  • Publications sub-menuPublications
    Hannah Arendt
    Subscribe to Amor Mundi

    “I've begun so late, really only in recent years, to truly love the world ... Out of gratitude, I want to call my book on political theories Amor Mundi.”

    • Publications
    • Amor Mundi
    • Quote of the Week
    • HA Yearbook
    • Podcast: Reading Hannah Arendt
    • Further Reading
    • Video Gallery
    • From Our Members
  • Events sub-menuEvents
    Hannah Arendt

    “It is, in fact, far easier to act under conditions of tyranny than it is to think.”

    —Hannah Arendt
    • HAC Events
    • Upcoming
    • Archive
    • JOY: Loving the World in Dark Times Conference
    • Bill Mullen Recitation Prize
  • Join sub-menu Join HAC
    Hannah Arendt

    “Political questions are far too serious to be left to the politicians.”

    • Join HAC
    • Become a Member
    • Subscribe
    • Join HAC
               
  • Search

Amor Mundi

Amor Mundi Home

 

Transcendence and Finitude: In Memory of Drucilla Cornell

12-18-2022

Roger Berkowitz

Drucilla Cornell died on Monday, Dec 12, 2022. Her obituary is here. Drucilla was a dear friend and also a constant supporter of the Arendt Center. She spoke at many of our annual conferences, including this talk on Dignity Jurisprudence in South Africa and a memorable panel with her, George Packer, Charles Murray, Kendall Thomas, Zephyr Teachout, and Philip Howard.  

Drucilla was one of the most unique and self-possessed people I’ve met, someone who could laugh and cry unapologetically, often in quick succession. Her friends whom she collected and loved included academics, trainers, and people she encountered daily in shops and on the street. Her annual Christmas party was a place to witness her loving community. It was to be held this year on Dec. 16th. Sadly, we must instead mourn Drucilla’s passing. Those who knew Drucilla miss her; we all are richer for her work. 

I met Drucilla in 1992. I told the story of our meeting and what it meant to me in an essay published in the book Imagining Law: On Drucilla Cornell, edited by Renée Heberle. 


At the end of my first year of graduate school, I was bored.  Faced with the reduction of thinking to politics on the one hand and the perversion of thinking into an indulgent pastime on the other,  I was experiencing firsthand the anti-intellectualism that now pervades our elite colleges and universities.  And yet, from out of the swamp that is the American academy, two discoveries gave me hope.  One was the encounter with the thought of Martin Heidegger through my mentor in Berkeley, Philippe Nonet.  The other was the work of Drucilla Cornell.  

I had never heard of Cornell when I was assigned The Philosophy of the Limit in a seminar in the Berkeley Rhetoric department in 1992.  What struck me in that book—struck me so hard that I sought out the author and, with her blessing, took a leave of absence from graduate school to journey back across the country to study with her for six months—what struck me was its force of thinking.

Philosophy and thinking matter for Cornell in the deepest sense of the word: philosophy itself “does have practical consequences; the practical consequences are precisely that law cannot inevitably shut out its challengers and prevent transformation, at least not on the basis that the law itself demands that it do so.” (Philosophy of the Limit, 165)  Unlike those who enlist philosophy in political causes, Cornell’s politics demands that she engage in the activity of philosophy itself.  By continually and rigorously pointing to the impossibility of a closed and actualized knowledge of the good, philosophy makes room for utopian dreams and justice.  The force of philosophy is to open a space for living justly.

Her devotion to the forceful importance of the idea of justice has led Cornell to be called a dreamer, a utopian, and an idealist.  She is unapologetically all three.  But what is often forgotten is that Cornell’s utopia is founded upon a relentless probing of her fundamental question: the possible unity of freedom and law—a unity that itself has its ground in the activity of thinking. 

This paper situates Cornell’s work within a specific tradition of thinking the belonging together of law and freedom. From Kant to Heidegger, the possibility of freedom amidst legal obligation is one of the central questions of political and ethical philosophy. Following both Kant and Heidegger, Cornell thinks freedom as the free embrace of obligation. At the same time, Cornell insists that contemporary thinkers take seriously the radical meaninglessness—the absence of both freedom and obligation—that threatens the modern condition. Suspicious of both Kant’s turn to a universal law of reason and Heidgger’s free embrace of man’s finite legal inheritance, Cornell accepts the increasingly widespread view that all meaning and all law are without ground. What is needed, Cornell argues, is a freely accepted embrace of law within and amidst the recognition of radical nihilism. Her insistence that finite beings can and must live in the paradoxical state of commitment to law in the face of the fact of law’s meaninglessness is the ethical center of her work.

Cornell’s philosophical inquiries gather their force from her conviction that the force of thinking can and does change the world. The force of thinking, in other words, is an active force that furthers justice. However, to say that the philosophy of the limit is the active force of justice is to locate Cornell’s thinking on the plane of ontology. This is to use a language that Cornell frequently does not.  Yet, if the philosophy of the limit is justice, and if justice is that part of law that must be vigilantly protected in its distinction from law, then the philosophy of the limit is a characterization of the essential way in which the law is.  Understood as the philosophy of the limit, law is the thinking of the absolute (the metaphysical dream of universal justice) from the position of human finitude (the limit).  As one crossroads where the absolute and the finite meet in human experience, law is a space of paradox—a space of the necessary encounter of the impossible dream of justice. 

Footer Contact
Contact HAC
Bard College
PO Box 5000
Annandale-on-Hudson, NY 12504
845-758-7878
[email protected]
Join the HAC
Become a Member
Subscribe to Amor Mundi
Join the Virtual Reading Group
Follow Us
Image for Twitter
Image for Facebook
Image for YouTube
Image for Instagram