Skip to main content.
Bard HAC
Bard HAC
  • About sub-menuAbout
    Hannah Arendt

    “There are no dangerous thoughts; thinking itself is dangerous.”

    Join HAC
    • About the HAC
      • About Hannah Arendt
      • Book Roger
      • Our Team
      • Our Location
  • Programs sub-menuPrograms
    Hannah Arendt
    • Our Programs
    • Courage to Be
    • Democracy Innovation Hub
    • Virtual Reading Group
    • Dialogue Groups
    • HA Personal Library
    • Affiliated Programs
    • Hannah Arendt Humanities Network
    • Meanings of October 27th
    • Lapham's Quarterly
  • Academics sub-menuAcademics
    Hannah Arendt

    “Storytelling reveals meaning without committing the error of defining it.”

    • Academics at HAC
    • Undergraduate Courses
  • Fellowships sub-menuFellowships
    HAC Fellows

    “Action without a name, a 'who' attached to it, is meaningless.”

    • Fellowships
    • Senior Fellows
    • Associate Fellows
    • Student Fellowships
  • Conferences sub-menuConferences
    JOY: Loving the World in Dark Times Conference poster

    Fall Conference 2025
    “JOY: Loving the World in Dark Times”

    October 16 – 17

    Read More Here
    • Conferences
    • Past Conferences
    • Registration
    • Our Location
    • De Gruyter-Arendt Center Lecture in Political Thinking
  • Publications sub-menuPublications
    Hannah Arendt
    Subscribe to Amor Mundi

    “I've begun so late, really only in recent years, to truly love the world ... Out of gratitude, I want to call my book on political theories Amor Mundi.”

    • Publications
    • Amor Mundi
    • Quote of the Week
    • HA Yearbook
    • Podcast: Reading Hannah Arendt
    • Further Reading
    • Video Gallery
    • From Our Members
  • Events sub-menuEvents
    Hannah Arendt

    “It is, in fact, far easier to act under conditions of tyranny than it is to think.”

    —Hannah Arendt
    • HAC Events
    • Upcoming
    • Archive
    • JOY: Loving the World in Dark Times Conference
    • Bill Mullen Recitation Prize
  • Join sub-menu Join HAC
    Hannah Arendt

    “Political questions are far too serious to be left to the politicians.”

    • Join HAC
    • Become a Member
    • Subscribe
    • Join HAC
               
  • Search

Amor Mundi

Amor Mundi Home

 

Three “Ideals”

06-21-2019

“Not the ideas themselves, but the non-religious concept of transcendence in philosophy […] is political in origin.”  —Hannah Arendt

 
Based on “a childhood fantasy about a land in thrall to the Olympic ideal,” Georges Perec’s 1975 novel W or The Memory of Childhood paints the picture of an island society locked in a relentless competition for survival and honor. In the novel, the inhabitants of this “nation of athletes” have organized all aspects of their community according to a strict hierarchy and schedule of contests between villages. All decisions are made in secret by the Central Government of W, which decides on the outcome of the annual “Games” with impunity. The purpose of these competitions is the “glorification of success” (89) and their losers are deprived not merely of recognition but of the island’s resources. Through constant competition, grueling training, starvation, and discriminatory practices that may randomly hit any contestant, that is, through a deliberate imposition of “organized injustice” (111), the society of W instills a sense of absolute unpredictability in its inhabitants. “The athlete must know that nothing is certain; he must expect anything, the best outcome or the worst. Decisions concerning him, whether they be trivial or vital, are taken without reference to him; he has no control over them” (117, Perec’s italics). What the initiation of athletes into the races effects is thus not the creation of a perfected species of man but the submission of all inhabitants under the dictate of a total lack of alternative. As in an inversion of Plato’s cave metaphor, the young novices of W realize that their notions of honorable battle and glorious rewards are a mere effect of sense deception, “magical notion[s]” that, upon actual confrontation, “appear[] before them in an intolerable light” (139).

At the very end of the novel, Georges Perec’s narrator intimates that his boyhood ideal, which he depicted in countless drawings of “sportsmen with stiff bodies and inhuman facial features” (163), resonates with a real document of totalitarianism, a document which he discovered many years after the fact. David Rousset’s L’Univers concentrationnaire (The Other Kingdom; 1946) describes the National Socialist concentration camps in the terms of a pseudo-athletic “game”: “The structure of the punishment camps is determined by two fundamental policies: no work but ‘sport’, and derisory feeding” (Rousset, cited in Perec 163). Rousset’s surreal provocation connects the language of exercise that most of his readers would recognize from more or less torturous gym class experiences to the utterly inassimilable idea of being fully exposed and subjected to the fantasy of an other: “In the small rectangular concrete yard, anything can be turned to sport: making men turn round very fast, under the whip, for hours on end; organizing a bunny-hop race, with the slowest to be thrown in the pond beneath the Homeric guffaws of the SS: having them repeat endlessly the exercise that consists of squatting on your heels, and then standing again, very fast, with both arms held out horizontally; forcing them to do press-ups fast [….]” (Rousset, cited in Perec 163, 4).

Along with his slightly earlier L’Univers concentrationnaire, Rousset’s personal account of the camps Les Jours de Norte Mort (1947) is among the most cited sources in “Totalitarianism in Power,” the next to last chapter of The Origins of Totalitarianism, and it is lauded as one of the “best reports on Nazi concentration camps” (439). Rousset’s “insights,” placed in quotation marks by Arendt to indicate that the very sense of penetrating the situation of the prisoner and of gaining knowledge about it is undermined (“‘knowledge of the disaster’ means knowledge as disaster”[1]), obviously made a lasting impression on Arendt, whose analysis follows that of Rousset in decisive ways.[2] Specifically, Arendt credits Rousset with being the first to realize that in the camps “everything is permitted” and it is this “everything,” this complete susceptibility to contingency on the one hand and vulnerability to total possibility as a principle which Perec captures with his island society.

But of course another text reverberates just under the surface of Perec’s fiction. As already indicated, it is Plato’s own vision of a perfectly regulated society in The Republic and, even more explicitly, in The Laws (Nomoi) that echoes throughout the novel. In the first text, Plato devises an ideal organization of life in the “cave” of worldly existence, which allows the philosopher-king to pursue truth undisturbed by the concerns of the city attended to by the well-educated guardians. In The Laws a written coda of rules governs every aspect of social life and is specifically intended to define the relationship between the rulers and the ruled. Following Arendt’s reading of this late Platonic dialogue, the text introduces, perhaps for the first time in Western philosophy, “rule as the all-important constituens of political affairs” (Modern Challenge, 327). As Arendt shows in the recently published manuscripts, lecture, and fragments that constitute The Modern Challenge to Tradition (2018),[3] an unfinished book project written in the prolific period between The Origins of Totalitarianism and The Human Condition, rule is not the only and certainly not the originary political category of government. Part of an ambitious attempt to rewrite the entire history of Western philosophy from Plato to Marx, her project situates the beginning of political thought in Plato’s cave allegory as the defining fantasy for the way we have come to represent the relationship between the common world and philosophical ideas. As is well known, the cave allegory describes the realm of human affairs as a mirage, a world of “darkness, confusion and deception” (Modern Challenge, 463) to be avoided by the truth-seeker. Arendt’s pointed thesis is that “[t]he beginning of political philosophy was made when the philosophers tried to rid themselves of and rule over the world of common human affairs” (ibid.). She thereby exposes that the concept of rule, which has since come to dominate our idea of politics (“who rules whom?” is the first question asked about any form of government), is not based on an experience of the polis but, on the contrary, reflects the desire of the philosopher. Starkly put, rule is introduced into thought about politics in order to “get rid” of the political — namely of the originally political characteristic of the common: action.

As a consequence, the philosopher’s utopia begins to resemble and foreshadow Perec’s and Rousset’s living hell. Thus the Nomoi, often regarded as the more democratic of Plato’s two visions of an ideal society, strikes Arendt as a particularly insidious amalgam of reality and fiction: “The state of the Nomoi does not only bear all characteristics of tyranny which the classical theory including Plato ever enumerated, it is even the most tyrannical utopy ever conceived. It is perhaps not exaggerated to speak of the hellish character of this state, with its merciless punishments, its nightly council and constant mutual spysystems. It is as though Plato, when he tried to re-write the Republic in a way which would blend the central story of the cave with the concluding myth of a hellish hereafter, succeeded only in devising a polity in which the myth of hell would be a horrible nightmarish reality” (327). By realizing his ideas as laws, which are intended only for those blind cave dwellers who will never see the truth, the philosopher secures his standing while maintaining his grip on the polis; “he becomes a ruler who is permanently in absentia” (326).

Crucially, in all three of these “utopias” — Perec’s, Rousset’s and even Plato’s — total possibility is joined with the “horrible omnipresence of laws” (517). That is, the very ubiquity of the standards imposed by the philosopher, imported as they are from the philosophical realm to the realm of human relations, appears to “fictionalize” the real. Everything becomes possible in such a community. The polis, in which contingency and relation are the irreducible facts of reality, is subjected to the transcendental ideas; speech and action must give way to “solitude” and “speechlessness.” Through the lens of Perec’s image of the Olympic ideal we can glimpse, darkly, the transcendence of the world as and in boundless possibility. Transcendence transcends, as it were, and what it transcends — or “skips over” — is relation: “a realm where everything seems to dissolve into relationships and to be relative by definition” (501). Rather than establishing its otherworldly claims, all that transcendence manages to supersede and leave behind is “the common world of living-together.” As such, Arendt marks transcendence itself as a political concept because its afterglow illuminates precisely the space it seeks to leave behind. “And it is here that the transcendence of the ideas has its origin; they are transcendent in terms of the world of the polis and no more so than the yardstick is transcendent in terms of the matter which it is supposed to measure; the standard necessarily transcends everything to which it is applied. Not the ideas themselves, but the non-religious concept of transcendence in philosophy, [sic] is political in origin” (501).

End Notes
[1] Ann Smock, “Translator’s Remarks,” in: Maurice Blanchot, The Writing of the Disaster (Nebraska, 1995): ix.
[2] In this context it is worth noting that Arendt’s treatment of eyewitness accounts in the same chapter — and her frequently cited remark on “dwelling on horrors” (OT 441) — should not be understood, as they often have been, as a dismissal of testimony or of thinking about totalitarianism. Thus, Deborah Nelson, like many others critics, misconstrues the issue when she presents the question of testimony in Origins as one that concerns the “relationship between thinking and reality.” Arendt clearly foregrounds that the problem is not thinking but understanding, which carries both associations of the knowability of disaster (“insight”) and, more particular to Arendt, of reconciliation, that is of understanding as a way of rooting myself in the world with others. In this sense, the issue is not that we cannot think totalitarianism but that we cannot live with it, cannot understand it as a feature of human plurality. Rather than “eras[ing] horror from the domain of thought” and “relegat[ing] [it] to the private realm,” as Nelson claims Arendt does, the entire point of her observations on witnessing is that it cannot serve to rebuild the common world. This becomes most obvious given her explicit reliance precisely on survivor accounts like those of Rousset and Bruno Bettelheim, who themselves stress over and over again that the camps’ main purpose was the destruction-qua-total-separation of the human. Thus, the camps effect the erosion of individuality, the uncommunicability of experience, and the degradation of prisoners and wardens alike into a “brotherhood of abjection” (Rousset in Arendt, 453). To be sure, only those who “have not actually been smitten in their own flesh […] can afford to keep thinking about horrors” and yet in their effort to understand what happened these “secondary witnesses” rely entirely on the “fearful imagination […] aroused by such reports” (OT 441). See Deborah Nelson, Tough Enough: Arbus, Arendt, Didion, McCarthy, Weil (Chicago, 2017): 64ff.
[3] Hannah Arendt, The Modern Challenge to Tradition: Fragmente eines Buches (Göttingen, 2018) is volume 6 in the Critical Edition of the Complete Works currently under way. Edited by Barbara Hahn and James McFarland, with support of Ingo Kieslich and Ingeborg Nordmann, the bi-lingual collection joins English and German texts and a critical apparatus of annotations, textual variants, and editorial notes as well as a soon to be released digital research tool for comparing different textual stages.

Jana Schmidt is a lecturer of literary theory at California State University, Los Angeles while working on her next manuscript, a book of encounters between German-Jewish exiles to America and African American artists and political activists from the 1940s to Black Power. She was a Postdoctoral Fellow at the Arendt Center in 2016/7 and taught at Bard as a Visiting Assistant Professor in the Humanities in 2017.

Footer Contact
Contact HAC
Bard College
PO Box 5000
Annandale-on-Hudson, NY 12504
845-758-7878
[email protected]
Join the HAC
Become a Member
Subscribe to Amor Mundi
Join the Virtual Reading Group
Follow Us
Image for Bluesky
Image for YouTube
Image for Instagram
Image for LinkedIn